Friday 25 November 2016

BOOK PREVIEW [coming in 2017] Sovereignty Conflicts and International Law and Politics: A Distributive Justice Issue. Chapter One: Introduction.

Sovereignty Conflicts and International Law and Politics

A Distributive Justice Issue

By Jorge E. Núñez





Chapter One

Sovereignty conflicts as a distributive justice dilemma


Introduction

It is arguably a truism in international law and politics that an ultimate 
sovereign, with a common legal bond or system of norms, will govern 
one territory with population. What would happen if that one territory 
and population had two ultimate and hierarchically equal sovereigns 
(legally speaking) and, at the same time, two valid sets of norms? 
Would it be possible, for instance, that Israel and Palestine had sovereign 
authority at the same time over Jerusalem? Would it be possible that 
Argentina and the United Kingdom were at one time sovereign over the 
territory and population of the Falkland/Malvinas Islands? If the answer 
were positive, what would the consequences be—in terms of territory, 
population, government and law?

Wednesday 23 November 2016

John Rawls: A Brief Account


Rawls is interested in A Theory of Justice in exploring what social policies should be implemented.  He adopts a non-utilitarian position and he accepts a broadly liberal individualistic approach, in which liberty and rights are important. His starting point is a claim about justice, based upon which we can work out how rights are to be assigned.



The problem of distributive justice

Solving the problem of distributive justice is often thought to present a conflict between two competing values:
a)              one is the value of liberty or freedom, which tells us that the less government interference in our lives the better, or at least this is what many people claim it tells us
b)             the other is equality, which tells us that unless there is a good reason to do otherwise, the benefits and burdens of social cooperation should be distributed equally

But since in most cases the benefits and burdens of social cooperation are not distributed equally, this requires some and sometime government interference in our lives, hence the supposed conflict with liberty


Ronald Dworkin has an argument that this supposed conflict is illusory—that our interest in liberty is no more than that—an interest, while our interest in equality is in fact a right, and that to the extent we have a right to certain basic liberties, these stem from notions of equality, not liberty

For a notion of justice see:
For distributive justice see:

John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice

The circumstances of justice

One of the first points that Rawls makes is that questions of distributive justice arise only under certain circumstances—what David Hume called the circumstances of justice (see David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature).

What are the circumstances of justice?

Limited resources and limited altruism.
Even if Rawls and Hume were both wrong about the circumstances of justice—we would still need principles of justice even under conditions of superabundance and unlimited altruism

Rawls’s criticisms of other theories of justice

Intuitionism

Intuitionism is the doctrine that there are an irreducible family of first principles (e.g. equality and freedom) which have to be weighed against one another in resolving questions of justice by asking which balance, in our considered judgment, is most just.

Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism avoids the priority problem by using the single criterion of the principle of utility
but Rawls criticizes utilitarianism on two grounds: it gives the good priority over the right and it ignores the distinctness of persons


Reflective Equilibrium and The Contractarian Method

Rawls argues that they would in fact choose two principles, which together he calls justice as fairness
a.         The first principle is that people are entitled to the most extensive system of basic liberties compatible with a similar system for everyone else
b.        The second principle is that social and economic inequalities are justified only if:
1.     They are attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity, and
2.     They benefit the least advantaged, meaning that some lesser degree of inequality would make the least advantaged members of society even worse off, a principle that Rawls calls the difference principle

The first principle has lexical priority over the second, meaning that the first must be fully satisfied before you apply the second, and thus you cannot sacrifice any aspect of basic liberty in favor of greater social and economic equality
c.         And the first part of the second principle—the principle of fair equality of opportunity—has lexical priority over the difference principle, meaning you cannot sacrifice fair equality of opportunity for greater social and economic equality either
Note: the first principle protects only the specified basic liberties, not liberty in general
The basic liberties referred to in the first principle are political liberty, freedom of thought, freedom of the person, and freedom from arbitrary arrest and seizure.

What are the strains of commitment?

The strains of commitment are the reasons why a party might violate an agreement or urge renegotiation
If a party is likely to violate their agreement to be bound by the difference principle or urge renegotiation once the veil of ignorance has been lifted, the strains of commitment will be excessive and the principles of justice selected from behind the veil of ignorance will be unstable.




Friday 11 November 2016

HLA Hart and The Concept of Law [Part 3 of 3]


With the last post of the series we will revise Hart's understanding of the relationship between law and morality, positivism and naturalism.


 For the previous posts refer to:

Jurisprudence: key authors in legal theory and political theory (a nutshell)

H.L.A. Hart and The Concept of Law (VERY briefly)

HLA Hart and The Concept of Law [Part 1 of 3]

HLA Hart and The Concept of Law [Part 2 of 3]




The relationship between law and morality

The relationship between law and justice 

Hart notes that there is long-standing distinction between various types of justice: distributive vs. corrective justice. Distributive justice is concerned with the background framework for transactions, while corrective justice focuses on specific occurrences. Distributive justice focuses on the individual vs. the collective, while corrective justice focuses on individual vs. individual.

In other words, distributive justice is about how we should allocate the burdens and benefits of social cooperation, while corrective justice is about how we should regulate and maintain the relations between individuals.
 
Substantive vs. formal or procedural or administrative justice. Substantive justice focuses on the outcome of particular cases, e.g. whether the outcome of the case is just under applicable moral standards. Formal justice focuses on principles of implementation, e.g. principles such as like cases should be treated alike.

 

The relationship between law and morality

Hart begins by noting some characteristics of morality and how these sometimes differ from the characteristics of law

a)      moral requirements always relate to important matters (moral standards restrict strong passions; social pressure is applied not only to comply with moral standards but also to teach them to others; without compliance far-reaching and distasteful changes would occur in the lives of individuals)

b)      moral rules evolve gradually, through slow decay or organic growth, they cannot be changed deliberately or abruptly by human fiat. In other words, unlike law, there are no rules of change associated with morality

c)      honourable intentions (including reasonable care) are always an excuse in the realm of morality, and moral blame attaches only to voluntary acts

d)     exhortation rather than force is the typical means of enforcing moral norms

e)      conformance is encouraged by appeal to the intrinsic value of compliance rather than the consequences of breach (e.g. punishment)

f)       there is no generally accepted rule of recognition for determining what the moral rules are

g)      unlike law, morality consists solely of primary rules that are either accepted by each individual or they are not 

 
Positivism and the minimum content of natural law

Legal Positivism is the simple contention that it is not necessary that laws reproduce or satisfy certain demands of morality, though in fact they have often done so.

No Legal Positivist claims that law cannot have moral content or that there is no moral significance to compliance with the rule of law but Legal Positivists deny that this must always be true.

Hart is an Inclusive Legal Positivist. 
 

There are four possible ways that the word "moral" can be used:

a)      to distinguish the moral from the immoral—i.e. evil. Legal positivists would say that law does not have to be morally commendable and can be wicked, whereas a natural law theorist would say that a wicked law is not law

b)      to distinguish moral from factual. This is the point of debate between Hart and Dworkin. Dworkin says the inquiry into what the law is a moral inquiry but Legal Positivists say that the process of law ascertainment can be purely factual as well as partially or wholly moral

c)      to distinguish moral from prudential: a moral decision is one that focuses on the interests of persons other than the decision-maker. A prudential decision focuses on the interests of the decision-maker. Positivists say that legal systems can be either prudential or moral, even though prudential systems might be pernicious

d)     to distinguish moral from amoral or non-moral. Something is non-moral if it is not subject to moral evaluation. A decision can be non-moral if it has no non-trivial impact on someone other than the decision-maker

 

While legal positivists deny any necessary connection between law and morality in the three ways set forth above, no legal positivist contends that law is non-moral.


The minimum content of natural law can be derived from these basic facts about human beings and their nature:

1.      approximate physical equality

2.      human vulnerability

3.      limited altruism and limited aggression

4.      limited resources

5.      limited understanding and strength of will

Given these basic facts about human beings and their nature, certain basic prohibitions are necessary for society to be viable:

a)      rules restricting physical violence

b)      rules requiring mutual forbearance and compromise

c)      rules protecting property and enforcing contracts

d)     rules imposing sanctions to ensure that those who voluntarily comply shall not be sacrificed to those who do not

These basic prohibitions coincide with moral prohibitions, so the two do converge and therefore any viable legal system will also have a basic moral core.


The minimum requirements of procedural law 

The minimum requirements of procedural law (sometimes called principles of legality) include:

1.      generality

2.      clarity

3.      publicity

4.      prospectivity

5.      consistency in application

Because there is a high degree of correlation between these procedural requirements and the principles of justice, this leads some people to contend law also has a procedural as well as a substantive moral core. But Hart says these procedural principles are not principles of morality, but principles of efficiency, needed to make any effort at social control effective.
 

The moral obligation to obey the law

Another potential front on which to find a connection between law and morality is with regard to the moral obligation to obey the law. There are two types of moral reasons for acting: a) obligatory—i.e. binding in the sense that in the absence of more weighty counter-veiling moral reason a failure to act is morally wrong; b) supererogatory—i.e. action is morally desirable but not morally required.

 



Law and morality in adjudication

Positivism is also attacked on the grounds that it fails to accurately describe what judges do when they decide cases in the penumbra. I.e. rather than simply mechanically apply the law, judges create the law as they think it ought to be, and this shows there is no separation between law and morals.

This is the primary argument made against Hart by Ronald Dworkin. But deciding penumbral cases according to what the law ought to be does not mean that a judge must apply a moral standard even though he may do so, for there are other criteria beside moral criteria the judge may apply in deciding what the law "ought" to be. So once again, while judges may apply moral criteria in exercising their discretion there is no conceptual reason why they must do so, so Hart denies that that there is any necessary connection between law and morality here either.


Hart's positive argument for separating law and morals 

The goal of legal positivism is to distinguish between what the law is and what it ought to be. Confusing these two separate questions creates two separate problems: a) it leads to anarchy in the sense that it encourages people to believe that a law which is not what it ought to be is not law and therefore may be disregarded; b) it stifles criticism of the law because it suggests that if something is the law than it is what it ought to be by definition.

Thus if the question of law and morals is not separated, there is the danger on the one hand that law will lose its authority because of a divergence of opinion on what the law ought to be and on the other hand escape criticism because the question of what is moral will be supplanted by the question of what is law.