Saturday 28 March 2020

How to do online academic research


In light of the COVID-19 situation, and being conscious many people may find it difficult to have access to academic source, a brief presentation about how to do free online academic research and find reputable free academic sources.
The presentation covers: 1. What is academic research? 2. Academic sources. 3. Academic search and online academic search. I explain how to use other more accessible and still reliable search engine tools you may use for your online academic research. You'll be able to find free academic sources from wherever you are. Dr Jorge E. Nunez Website: https://drjorge.world Facebook: https://www.facebook.com/DrJorge.World Youtube: https://www.youtube.com/drjorge Twitter: London1701

Friday 20 March 2020

ASAP-Juris North 2nd UK-Russian Symposium on “Jurisprudence and Sovereignty” (Manchester, April 2020)


Over the past few days, we have been working with our fellow organisers in Russia to fully assess the potential impacts of the COVID-19 pandemic on our event. After carefully considering the situation, we have come to the conclusion the most reasonable choices are to postpone the main event and to run an online set of presentations. 

MAIN EVENT POSTPONED until further notice:

We are sure you share our disappointment regarding this unavoidable postponement. At this stage, our contingency plans are to postpone the main event until further notice and to still run some sessions on Friday 24th and Saturday 25th April online. 

ONLINE EVENT: Friday 24th and Saturday 25th April

Those speakers who are kindly coming together to the online platform will be presenting their work from their respective locations and the audience will still have access to these live presentations without any risk to their health and wellbeing. 

PUBLICATION: 

In addition to the online event, we’ll select the best papers to be published as an “ASAP Journal special issue.” Details about submissions, deadlines, review process, selection/rejection of the manuscript, etc. will follow.
ASAP Journal can be found at: http://journalasap.org/index.php/asap (the link works better using Google Chrome). 
On behalf of the organisers and presenters, many thanks for your understanding and collaboration. We are all working tirelessly to ensure we firm up a date for the postponed 2020 main Symposium. In the meantime, we’ll keep you posted about the online event on 24th and 25th April 2020 and the ASAP Journal special issue. 
Note: we expect to have the final details about the online event and the ASAP Journal special issue by end March.

Friday 13 March 2020

Territorial disputes: Crimea (Part 20) [Post 85]


Crimea and the Egalitarian Shared Sovereignty: Final Words
To recapitulate, we have two sovereign States Russia and Ukraine claiming sovereignty over Crimea, the third populated territory in our model. The three populations through their representatives agreed on sharing sovereignty over Crimea.

They understand that they are dealing with many issues such as activities or goods, and these many issues imply both benefits and burdens. So, to ask all of them to contribute equally and receive an equal return is not the solution. 
Neither is it for the better off in any given activity to contribute more and the least advantaged in any other activity to receive a larger benefit. They may either lead to domination or to continuous assistance. Because they do also know that they will maintain the agreement under the three pre-requisites, they keep their reciprocal non-interference and consider themselves reciprocally equals. In addition to this, they know it is a targeted agreement only referring to the third territory: this is not an agreement based on humanitarian reasons, domestic or global justice.

In order to make the egalitarian shared sovereignty work by acknowledging the many differences amongst the parties, we have to foresee the possibility that one party (or some of them) may contribute more and the other parties considerably less, so it would imply an unbalanced relationship that may indeed lead to a) domination or neo-colonialism; or b) continuous assistance.

Thereby, egalitarian shared sovereignty understood as a balancing principle amongst Crimea, Russia, and Ukraine—bearing in mind their differences—implies:
Crimea, Russia, and Ukraine have all the same right to participate in every aspect of the sovereignty over Crimea. That is to say, they all have the opportunity to present and amend proposals in relation to every aspect of the sovereignty over Crimea (egalitarian consensus principle). 
Crimea shares in equal portions natural resources with Russia and Ukraine. Russia shares in equal portions the means for their exploration and exploitation with Crimea and Ukraine. And Ukraine, because of their geographical location, will grant special privileges for both Crimean and Russian enterprises only related to the exploitation of natural resources in Crimea (or any other activity but it must be related to Crimea).

Indeed, either Crimea or Ukraine may have issues in exploiting at the same level of efficiency as Russia their shares of natural resources. Hence, Russia must make sure that both the other agents reach the same level of exploitation or divide the benefits resultant amongst the three parties equally in the meantime, that is it is a targeted shared model.

The principle can be seen in a larger picture across the board with different activities. At first, the smaller and the larger the contribution, the smaller and the larger the return respectively. But as the agreement aims to avoid domination (secure non-interference) and has a target, it is to be expected a more evenly shared contribution-return relationship amongst the parties will emerge in the long term.
In the example, at first Crimea would be defended by Russia, and the latter would as well contribute to the exploitation of the natural resources in the peninsula (principle of efficiency). In principle, Russian would receive a larger share of the resultant benefits—the larger the contribution, the larger the return, and let us remember that Russia is contributing towards both defence and exploitation of natural resources in a larger manner than the other two agents (input-to-output ratio principle). This covers the burdens-benefits part.

But, as we have a targeted agreement, Russia must make sure both Crimea and Ukraine reach relatively the same level for the defence of the third territory and the exploitation of natural resources (equilibrium proviso). It is then when the contributions amongst the three will be more even as well as the returns.

Meanwhile, and in order to lessen the gap between contributions and benefits, Ukrainians could use the difference they have in their favour: geographically proximity means a more accessible bilateral commerce with Crimea, faster and possibly more effective response in case of international threat or attack, etc., things that Russia cannot offer.

Moreover, as the first and second pre-requisite grants non-domination and non-political liberties, different religious beliefs between could not be used for the advantage or disadvantage of any of the populations. That is because they are in a certain order of priority.
This principle is applicable only to sovereignty over the third territory and to what concerns the third territory (and all that this implies). Thus, the principle and the pre-requisites are lexically ordered (Rawls 1999, pp. 53 in fine and 54 supra) both mutually and in relation to the egalitarian shared sovereignty. In other words, no transgression of: a) non-domination or non-interference; b) the basic non-political liberties; and c) the principles recognised by the law of peoples, is allowed under any excuse or reason even if that means not fulfilling the egalitarian shared sovereignty.

The lexical order dictates the priority amongst the pre-requisites and the principle if there is a conflict in practice. Indeed, the pre-requisites and the ‘egalitarian shared sovereignty’ are intended as a single conception and not to work individually. However, reality may show instances in which to apply the principle could go against one or both pre-requisites.
Therefore, the lexicographic or lexical preference ordering applies. That is because the agents will have multiple criteria motivating their choices. As they will have a ranking of priorities, the choice amongst the different alternatives will follow the highest criterion. Inversely, by respecting the egalitarian shared sovereignty we know the agents will take into account both pre-requisites.

The main reason to proceed this way is to secure a real ‘equal footing’. Indeed, as a result of the lexical order basic rights will only be compared with other basic rights, powers and prerogatives with other powers and prerogatives, and so on. Thereby, arrangements that could imply trading basic non-political liberties for, for example, the exploitation of natural resources, could be avoided. So, none of the agents could use their relative better position at the expense of any of the other parties.

NOTE: This post is based on Jorge Emilio Núñez, Territorial Disputes and State Sovereignty. International Law and Politics (Routledge 2020).
Previous published research monograph about territorial disputes and sovereignty by the author, Jorge Emilio Núñez, Sovereignty Conflicts and International Law and Politics: A Distributive Justice Issue London and New York: Routledge, Taylor and Francis Group, 2017.

NEXT POST: Northern Ireland (available online from Monday 27th April 2020)

Friday 13th March 2020
Dr Jorge Emilio Núñez
Twitter: @London1701

Thursday 12 March 2020

Territorial disputes: Crimea (Part 19) [Post 84]





Crimea, the Egalitarian Shared Sovereignty, and Utopia

Consider a group of people living on a peninsula named Crimea. The majority of Crimean people are Orthodox Christian but there is a large majority of Muslims (there are some other minor religions represented as well).

Although the territory is small in size, it is highly rich in natural resources. However, it is assumed here they do not possess the means for its exploration and exploitation and hence depend on third parties to do it. They do not have any means to defend the peninsula. At the center of the Black Sea, Crimea faces directly Russia, Ukraine, Turkey, Georgia, Rumania, and Bulgaria. Finally, the sovereignty of the peninsula is currently claimed by the Russian Federation and Ukraine.

 

Ukraine is a medium size sovereign State with a medium size population, mainly Orthodox Christian. This country is situated linked to Crimea by land and it is also rich in natural resources. Ukrainians have their own means of defense.

 

Russia one of the largest sovereign States in the world in terms of territorial size, but not densely populated (although the population is larger in relation to those of Crimea and Ukraine). Russians are mainly Orthodox Christian with other several religious minorities. The territory is rich in natural resources. The Crimean people have very limited means to defend their territory. Geographically, they are located in the continent adjacent to Russia and Ukraine, so mainland Russia and Ukraine share with Crimea part of the continental shelf.

 

The following paragraphs give a more detailed account of the example.

 

  • Crimea is strategically important for both Russia and Ukraine because of its location on the Black Sea, and hence the most advantaged in that respect (difference in Crimea’s advantage). However, it is the least advantaged in terms of territorial and population size, and defense. Crimea is key in Ukraine’s plans for energy independence and gas diversification strategy. The peninsula is important for Russia in many aspects such as natural resources and geopolitical location (for example, as a base for Russian navy).

 

  • Russia is the most advantaged in terms of wealth and defence (differences in Russia’s favour), the least advantaged in terms of geopolitical location, and in particular less advantaged than Ukraine in relation to their geographical proximity to Crimea.

 

  • Ukraine is the most advantaged in terms of geographical proximity to Crimea (difference in Ukraine’s favour), but less advantaged than Russia in terms of wealth and defence.

 
Equality and the difference principle applied sensu stricto
Before reviewing how the egalitarian shared sovereignty may work in this situation, let us see briefly how the principle of equality and the difference principle result when applied sensu stricto in this case.

 

If we applied equality strictly, they would all receive equal benefits and contribute equally towards the burdens. How would Ukraine fulfil its duty to defend Crimea? How would Crimean people defend themselves? The same could be said about natural resources because although Crimea, Russia, and Ukraine would receive the same share in terms of ownership, Crimean people would not have the means to exploit them. Several other implications could be drawn but we have already made a point. It is both unreasonable and unfair to expect three parties with different comparative situations in many different areas to contribute in an equal manner or to receive an equal return.

 

Nevertheless, to apply the difference principle in the same form may have similar consequences. Let us assume that overall Ukraine is the least advantaged in terms of natural resources, so they will receive a larger share. Crimea is less advantaged than Russia and Ukraine in terms of defense, so Russia will provide the means to defend the third territory. But Ukriane is less advantaged than Russia in terms of wealth, the natural resources in its territory are not part of the agreement so they are not under discussion, and they do not have means to defend the third territory to the same extent Russia does. Would they have to receive a larger share of the benefits resultant from the exploitation of natural resources in Crimea with means provided by Russia? Indeed, this seems unacceptable.

 

NOTE: This post is based on Jorge Emilio Núñez, Territorial Disputes and State Sovereignty. International Law and Politics (Routledge 2020).

Previous published research monograph about territorial disputes and sovereignty by the author, Jorge Emilio Núñez, Sovereignty Conflicts and International Law and Politics: A Distributive Justice Issue London and New York: Routledge, Taylor and Francis Group, 2017.

 

NEXT POST: Crimea and the Egalitarian Shared Sovereignty: Final Words

 

Thursday 12th March 2020

Dr Jorge Emilio Núñez

Twitter: @London1701




Wednesday 11 March 2020

Thank you all from Juris North


A day like today, 5 years ago, we had our first Juris North discussion with Iain Brassington (The University of Manchester) here in Manchester. On behalf of Verónica, William, Peter, Michael and Jorge, thank you all​. 
​ 
Juris North FACTS
  • ​First discussion on 11th March 2015. Since then, we've had at least one monthly discussion each term (January-March and August-December) . So, 11th March 2020 it's our 5th anniversary.
  • ​Five chairs:
A legal and political philosophy discussion group, in collaboration with the Universities of Durham, Hull, Liverpool, Manchester, Manchester Metropolitan​ and Surrey.  
Durham: Prof. Dr William Lucy
Hull (now Northumbria): Dr Peter Cserne
Liverpool: Prof. Dr Michael Gordon
Manchester: Dr Jorge E. Núñez
Surrey: Prof. Dr Verónica Rodríguez-Blanco
  • ​Partnerships: 
Internal partnerships with other Schools within MMU-e.g. Sociology, Philosophy, and Criminology.
External partnerships, with key players in HE in the UK and abroad. For example, with our peers in Oxford, Cambridge, and Edinburgh, creating a network of collaboration in which Juris North represents the North-West region.
Also, a solid partnership with IVR’s UK branch. IVR, the Association for Legal Philosophy and Social Philosophy, is the main  body nationally and internationally of its kind. And now, in partnership with ASAP (Academics Stand Against Poverty)​ http://academicsstand.org 

  • ​Audience (1 to 200+): 
Students, academics, public in general. Depending on the theme, date/time, from one to 200+ people in the audience.

  • ​​Presenters (circa 100 in 5 years):
National and international: all of them pay their own expenses in terms of travel and accommodation. Nationally, from UCL, Edinburgh, Warwick, Manchester, Liverpool, etc. Internationally, from Argentina, Brazil, United States, Romania, Greece, Russia, Poland, Norway, Syria, Israel, and many others.
Institutions: Schools/Faculties of law, political sciences, philosophy, etc.

  • Events:​
  1. ​Monthly discussions.
  2. @cademia: reading, researching and writing group. We're now supporting the Manchester Law Journal at MLS.
  3. ​Yearly events. For example,
2016 First UK-Russian Symposium "Jurisprudence and Sovereignty" FYI the 2016 Symposium resulted in a monograph entitled «Sovereignty and Jurisprudence» edited by Marianna Muravyeva and Jorge E. Nunez, Springer, Forthcoming 2020.
2018 ASAP-Juris North Conference "Global Justice and Crisis" http://academicsstand.org/asap-jn-conference-global-justice-and-crisis-manchester-saturday-6th-october-930am-5pm/
2020. ASAP-Juris North Second K-Russian Symposium "Jurisprudence and Sovereignty"April 2020. Call for papers attached.

NOTE: all our events are free of charge thanks to our host HE Institutions. 

  • ​Call for papers: ongoing.

PHOTOS

You may find some pictures on our Twitter account @NorthJuris 


THANK YOU ALL
Jorge

Dr Jorge Emilio Núñez 
t: @London1701 | t: @NorthJuris


On 14 June, I'll run the Rio marathon on behalf of Fundação Angelica Goulart. For info. on how to help us https://drjorge.world/public-impact/

Territorial disputes: Crimea (Part 18) [Post 83]


Crimea, negotiations and “similar” or “identical” shares of sovereignty
The egalitarian shared sovereignty solves sovereignty conflicts because it simply acknowledges the facts, because:

a) that sovereignty conflicts and sovereignty are complex issues;
b) that complexity is given by these issues being constituted by activities and goods that imply both benefits and burdens; and
c) that the claiming agents are most probably in very different comparative situations in many senses.

We do not have the problem of defining equality because we are not referring to the parties but to the target, the third territory. All the parties receive equal shares of sovereignty since these shares are ideal (they only represent their right to equal benefits and the obligation to equal contributions and only in what is referred to the third territory).

Thereby, if they can make equal contributions, they will receive equal benefits. We do not even think of their relative situations as members of the international society. They are equal or not in as much as it is referred to the target, the third territory.

Coincidentally, if they cannot fulfil their obligations to the same extent, their returns will be affected. It is when the qualitative differences come into play. And they are referred to the situation of each of the parties in relation to a specific good in what matters only to the third territory.

To give an example, if a party A cannot defend the third territory because it does not have any means of defence, then it cannot contribute (so its return will be lessened). 
As we have two pre-requisites and a targeted agreement, the other two parties B and C will have to assist party A in as much as their assistance is needed to let party A have a similar contribution in regards to that specific good or activity (in the example, parties B and C will assist in the development of the means of defense of party A, but only in as much as it is necessary for the defense of the third territory).

Indeed, the egalitarian shared sovereignty provides for the legitimacy of initial differences in the benefits and burdens of the parties in a way that the equality principle does not. So, when we reach the ultimate egalitarian shared sovereignty goal of equilibrium amongst the parties, there will be no problem in knowing what ‘equal shares’ require since these will be similar shares of each of the goods relevant to sovereignty (output) amongst three agents with similar level of use of their respective shares (input).

I use the term “similar” rather than “identical” when I refer to the final shares since there will be obviously some elements that because of factual restrictions or limitations cannot be equally or identically used, or at least not to the same extent in the literal meaning of these expression such as geographical proximity.

Conclusion: Crimea, the Egalitarian Shared Sovereignty, and Utopia

Following the previous paragraphs, the next post will introduce a hypothetical situation in order to show how the egalitarian shared sovereignty works in the context of the Crimean sovereignty dispute. The aim of this example is to demonstrate how by acknowledging certain features and by applying the criteria mentioned before, a shared sovereignty model can work, at least in theory. Note that the following paragraphs will use an oversimplified view with reference to some key points usually controversial in any sovereignty conflict and that therefore are present in the Crimean case.

NOTE: This post is based on Jorge Emilio Núñez, Territorial Disputes and State Sovereignty. International Law and Politics (Routledge 2020).
Previous published research monograph about territorial disputes and sovereignty by the author, Jorge Emilio Núñez, Sovereignty Conflicts and International Law and Politics: A Distributive Justice Issue London and New York: Routledge, Taylor and Francis Group, 2017.

NEXT POST: Crimea, the Egalitarian Shared Sovereignty, and Utopia

Wednesday 11th March 2020
Dr Jorge Emilio Núñez
Twitter: @London1701