The European Union as a whole and Greece
in particular are experiencing another crisis in, what it seems, a never-ending
downfall. Earlier this week, I had the opportunity to be present and deliver a
presentation at the 2015 ATINER Law Summit in Athens. My presentation entitled “Sovereignty
Conflicts as a Distributive Justice Issue: the Egalitarian Shard Sovereignty as
a New Mode of Governance” was intended to deal with sovereignty conflicts such
as Falklands, Gibraltar, Crimea, Jerusalem, and many others within the ideal
theory—i.e. as opposed to non-ideal according to Rawls. Therein, it had little
to do with Greece, the European Union, the crisis… or at least, I had thought
so.
When the questions came, after the
presentation was done and dusted, one in particular was key: How do Germany and
Greece “share sovereignty”? My first reaction was: this presentation is not
about already settled issues in legal and political theory. In fact, it has
nothing to do with the European Union. But, second later, I realised a key
issue in untangling the European Union crisis has undoubtedly to do with the
unbalanced power-sharing. Let me explain myself:
What does it mean to “share sovereignty”?
Advocates of this position apply the label ‘shared sovereignty’ to situations
in which there is one sovereign State (usually a weak one) and an international
organisation or another State ‘helping’ it in one way or another. In this case,
they define it as follows:
“[s]hared-sovereignty
entities are created by a voluntary agreement between recognised national
political authorities and an external actor such as another state or a regional
or international organization”. Moreover, “[s]uch arrangements can be limited
to specific issues areas like monetary policy or the management of oil
revenues.” [Krasner, 2005]
Firstly, it is a voluntary actual
agreement; secondly, not all the parties need to be sovereign States (they can
be recognised national political authorities, regional or international
organisations); thirdly, it can be limited to specific areas (the examples
given are related to economy and finance).
Some authors assert that weak states could observe this proposal as a
solution to their problems since—they maintain—“[l]eft to their own devices,
collapsed and badly governed states will not fix themselves because they have
limited administrative capacity, not least with regard to maintaining internal
security.” [Krasner, 2004]
Therefore, international organisations or strong States would be supporting the
development in certain areas of States that for whatever cause were considered
weak.
There are several reasons that are at best
problematic with this conception of ‘shared sovereignty.’ The implications of
defining in such a fashion ‘shared sovereignty’ do not agree with a just and
fair way of dealing with sovereignty issues. Whilst this account of ‘shared
sovereignty’ is theoretically intended to assist weak States and hence may be
considered useful—even fair—at first glance, it is both too narrow and too
ample. Too narrow in the sense that the weak State sees its actions being
dictated by external authorities without much internal input; too ample since
the strong agent has the prerogative to be involved in affairs of the weak one
without control other than its own good will. For although this model involves
already ‘recognised national political authorities’, these scholars presuppose
that collapsed or badly governed communities (weak States) cannot dictate for
themselves proper policies and create efficient institutions to achieve a
sustainable development. So the way to fix these realities—they propose—is to
let the strong States be involved in the internal affairs of the weak ones.
Yet, instead of presenting shared sovereignty this appears to be a means to
dictate to another supposedly
sovereign State how to proceed under certain circumstances. Furthermore, what
is clear is the fact that both sovereign States—the weak and the strong
one—would not have the same level of authority: the strong sovereign State
would be determining the advisable actions to be followed by the weak
‘sovereign’ State. In other words, the ‘neo-colonial shared sovereignty’ (as I
prefer to call this conception) is uni-directional and unequal (only one of the
involved States is the real sovereign, maybe not de jure but, at least, de
facto) resulting in one agent dictating the other’s internal policies.
Those who are in favour of ‘shared
sovereignty’—so defined—maintain that humanitarian reasons support this form of
international aid. Violation of human rights, natural disasters and weak
economies are only examples of many actual circumstances that make the internal
situation of some sovereign States highly volatile. Nevertheless, behind this
aura of humanitarian aid strong States would be interfering in the internal
affairs of their weak peers. By applying the ‘shared sovereignty’ label in this
way, both States seem to be equally sovereign with one of them—the strong
one—assisting the other one by being involved in its internal affairs. But
although it may seem at first glance that they are equal sovereign powers, they
are only equal in terms of their de jure
sovereignty; de facto, one of the
States is determining, or advising, or forcing, or instructing, the other
State’s way of addressing its internal issues. From that angle, these States
are not sharing sovereignty; in fact, only one of them is the ultimate
authority in regard to certain issues which are actually supposed to be in the
sovereign sphere of the other one. Indeed, the ‘sharing’ may be, or become,
involuntary.
Consequently, to understand ‘shared
sovereignty’ as a way in which a strong State ‘assists’ a weak peer does not
seem to agree with the nature of the concept itself. The whole theory has been
developed so as to justify what may result in a violation of State sovereignty.
If ‘shared sovereignty’ is the global
tendency with the European Union as the most developed example, the aim should
be to offer all the involved international agents a real equal footing at
the outset, so as to reach a just and fair final agreement in which all parties
are taken into account and have an actual (not only theoretical) say with regards their internal and external
affairs.